A Brief Colonial History Of Ceylon(SriLanka)
Sri Lanka: One Island Two Nations
A Brief Colonial History Of Ceylon(SriLanka)
Sri Lanka: One Island Two Nations
(Full Story)
Search This Blog
Back to 500BC.
==========================
Thiranjala Weerasinghe sj.- One Island Two Nations
?????????????????????????????????????????????????Saturday, September 1, 2018
Even more cuts: Busting Locke
- During these centuries, moreover, the State, which had passed power from the landed aristocracy to the industrialists, sided with the latter
- From “liberties” to “liberty”: the world according to Hobbes, Grotius, and Bodin was now secularised, subject to no will higher than that of the sovereign
It is tempting to view the 17th and 18th centuries as eras of progress,
reform, and enlightenment. Intellectuals and academics the world over
tout this period of history as a sort of apotheosis for Western Europe,
in which the West took over from the East in the domain of the material
and the philosophical.
That this shift coincided with the rise of colonialism and
industrialisation is no cause for wonderment, given that such a paradigm
transformation in philosophy needed a firm economic base, exploitative
and oppressive, but at the same time advertised as liberal and
inevitable to the exploited and oppressed. Take any thinker from these
centuries and read into what they thought about rights, duties, and
obligations. You will come across the same worldview: the world is
composed of individuals, but this does not forbid the State from
intervening in their (political) rights in the interests of economic
freedom.
The economic, then, determined the general philosophical consensus
regarding the individual during this time. This is true of roughly every
society and is valid for every historical juncture, be it in the West
or the East. From Thomas Hobbes, Hugo Grotius, and Jean Bodin, history
gave way to John Locke, who provided the perfect backdrop for the rising
nouveau riche in England through a variant of the Social Contract which
balanced the subject with the sovereign: “He was not an enemy of
political authority.” During these centuries, moreover, the State, which
had passed power from the landed aristocracy to the industrialists,
sided definitively with the latter. The bourgeoisie had been the first
revolutionary to rebel against the feudal manorial order; once history
passed over to the market, he became the reactionary.
Liberty: Last week I pointed out that the word had a connotation
different to the one we take for granted today. To sum up, and to add to
what I wrote: When the world entered the epoch that paved the way for
capitalism (in Fernand Braudel’s analysis, between the 15th and the 18th
centuries), powerful towns gave way to even more powerful nation
states. These nation states (precursors to the modern State, with a
capital S) bloomed in regions where towns were not powerful: Spain,
France, and Britain. The world had known of “liberties” until then,
wielded by powerful groups against the less powerful (although when the
economic tide turned, the less powerful, namely the peasantry, got the
upper hand). It was a relatively peaceful era, demarcated however by
ignorance, fanaticism, complacency, and slowness (between the 9th and
the 16th centuries, writes Professor Ha-Joon Chang, income per capita in
Western Europe grew at 0.12% per year). The transition from towns to
nation states came about through war and its “imperious needs”,
artilleries and armies. By the end of the 17th century, Europe was
waging war on itself, usurping the monarch and turning him into a
constitutional figurehead. The sovereignty of the State was soon above
all laws, all kings, now.
Europe, hitherto regional, and limited to centres of urban power, became Europe: national, territorial.
From “liberties” to “liberty”: the world according to Hobbes, Grotius,
and Bodin was now secularised, subject to no will higher than that of
the sovereign. The sovereign was, however, subject to Natural and Divine
Law. Even that changed: “Etiamsi daremus non esse Deum,” wrote Grotius,
speaking for the new world order: even if God did not exist, the
natural law prevailed. Divine law, though not disparaged or relegated or
thrown away, was subsumed by the new secularism, and so soon enough,
when the constitutional monarchy made it possible for the bourgeoisie to
wield their clout in the parliament and outside it, “theism” (which
held that God had the last word on material affairs) gave way to the at
times confusing, convoluted “deism” (which held that God created man,
but did not intervene in those material affairs). The man who stood
between the secular absolutists of the 17th century and the deist
liberals of the 18th century, which saw “liberties” give way to an
amorphous and rather highly contentious-as-to-what-it-really-meant
“liberty”, was Locke. It seems superfluous to devote an entire essay on
the man, but it is at the same time essential that we do so.
Much has been written on Locke. Some contend that he was an apologist
for ruthless commercial capitalism. Some point out that his tirades
against exploitation were at odds with his ownership of stock in slave
trading companies (remember, this was an era when one man’s right over a
multitude was taken for granted). Some, not a few, contend that by
distinguishing between sovereigns and tyrants, he gave the perfect
excuse for Western powers, today, to differentiate between pro-Western
dictators (who are favoured) and “anti-Western” democrats (who are
deposed).
Whichever way you look at it, however, you cannot discount his influence
on a period of history which defined the length and breadth of
modernity. Western Europe owes it to Locke for its conception of
liberalism, more specifically classical liberalism (which is what this
series is about), and so does the world’s most vibrant “democracy” (note
the asterisks), the United States of America. The truth is that without
Locke, and his Two Treatises, there would not have been a Declaration
of Independence.
He had it both ways: the subject could revolt against the sovereign, but the sovereign could be deposed only if he had lost the right to rule: “A tyrant has no authority.” The bedrock of the State was political authority, and authority flowed from property.
He had it both ways: the subject could revolt against the sovereign, but the sovereign could be deposed only if he had lost the right to rule: “A tyrant has no authority.” The bedrock of the State was political authority, and authority flowed from property.
Unlike Hobbes, civil society for Locke was not preceded by a state of
nature “nasty, brutish, and short”. On the contrary, what had preceded
it was an Eden in which liberty flourished. As the population grew,
however, so did man’s wants, and the Eden which had subsisted until then
was threatened by property: there were just too many individuals, and
too little land. It was to resolve this issue that he willingly gave up
his liberty, and let his Eden fall: in return for his liberty, which was
not really taken away from him, only reduced, he would be ensured
ownership over his land. The secular absolutists of the preceding
century had viewed the sovereign as a totalitarian tamer; Locke viewed
him as a firm mediator. In doing so, he sanctified the instrument
through which the sovereign became that mediator, private property.